| | Sherman wrote, Obviously, if an individual makes a "bad" choice it is "bad" from your point of view, not from his, or he wouldn't make it. Why else would a person make a "bad" choice? (And please don't say: "Out of ignorance," unless you mean to profess perfect knowledge is possible. And please don't say: "Out of ignorance of reality," unless you mean to profess perfect knowledge of reality is possible.) What do you mean by "perfect knowledge of reality"? Knowledge is knowledge. I can know that a person who is addicted to methamphetamines, for example, is ruining his health and destroying his life. I don't need to be omniscient in order to know that. I can also know that the Nazis who murdered millions of Jews made bad (immoral) choices. I don't have to be omniscient in order to know that. Are you seriously questioning our ability to know that some choices are objectively better or worse than others? A person who gets drunk and then drives recklessly, endangering his own life as well as the lives of others has made a bad choice. The fact that he may, in some foggy stupor, THINK that it is a good choice does not alter that fact. Earlier in this thread a commentator gave an example of an individual who makes a financial trade which results in his economic ruin and the deterioration of his health. This commentator said it was a "bad" choice. Is such a trade a "bad" choice from your point of view? It seems so with the benefit of hindsight, but at the point the trade is made the "goodness" or "badness" of the trade is not clear. We have to make a distinction between what can be judged bad ex ante, and what can only be judged bad ex post. The "bad" trade that you mentioned was not evidently capable of being known as bad until after the fact. However, for some trades the knowledge that they're bad or unwise is available before the trade is made. Some stocks are bad investments ex ante. If, for example, you put your life savings into a penny stock with no knowledge of the company or the likely success of its product, then you are making a bad investment ex ante, and your investment can be criticized as an unreasonable or objectively bad decision. On the other hand, a decision can be a good one -- reasonable under the circumstances --and still turn out bad, ex post. Man is not infallible and must act within the limits of his knowledge. Again, why would a person knowingly make a trade that is "bad?" Even if he doesn't know, we can say that information on what constitutes a good or bad investment was available at the time, and that he should have known. How does one know at the time a choice is made whether or not that choice will "maximize" one's happiness? One can acquire that knowledge by taking the time to learn more about the risks and the consequences before making a decision. It seems reasonable to me to believe that an individual who makes a choice makes it because he believes that choice will "maximize" his happiness. It seems reasonable to me to believe that in a vast majority of cases of such individual choices there is no obvious choice which, objectively, could be shown at the time to "maximize" the chooser's happiness. Not true. People make demonstrably bad choices all the time, much of it their own fault, because they haven't carefully considered the alternatives before choosing to act. People act on impulse and do things that are stupid and irresponsible -- things which they later regret and which they wouldn't have done if they had taken the time to think about the likely consequences of their actions. To say that we can't criticize their behavior, because we don't "possess perfect knowledge of reality" is ridiculous. Nobody believes that, except perhaps a few diehard ethical subjectivists. And, to your credit, even you don't believe it, because you think that some economic policies are better than others and should be chosen, even if they're not.
I wrote, "The point I am making is that there are certain objective conditions that are conducive to one's happiness, even if people sometimes ignore them and make bad choices or decisions. Do you disagree with this? Do you believe, for example, that a drug addict is living an optimal lifestyle, one that promotes his happiness and well being, simply because he happens to have chosen it?" The point I am making is that Austrian economics (as I understand it) cannot logically deduce "that there are certain objective conditions that are conducive to one's happiness" from it's original premise (man acts with purpose). [If you can make such a deduction, I would be happy to read it.] Austrian economics is a deductive science built on the foundation of its original premise. Thus, whether I agree or disagree that "objective conditions" exist, is irrelevant to the science of Austrian economics.
Yes, as a consequentialist I would argue that "certain objective conditions" "are conducive to one's happiness," but I would have to argue this point from the value-laden point of view of consequentialism, not from the deductive point of view of Austrian economics. Well, then, you are a budding Objectivist. Nice to have you onboard, Sherman! :-)
I wrote: "That term ["eugenics"] can be used simply to refer to the improvement of human life through genetic engineering and to the elimination of inherited diseases." Come on now, no smuggling concepts. It is clear from the context of my post I was referring to eugenics as it existed in the earlier 20th century. There is little doubt that eugenics then was a normative "science." With the benefit of hindsight it is easy for you to scoff that eugenics then did not comport to "empirical reality," but it was not so easy then, especially when the criticisms of real scientists then were labeled by eugenicists as "wrong" in the moral sense. As I understand your argument, you're criticizing the science of eugenics on the basis of its normativity per se, rather than on the basis of its flawed theories. You're saying that it was wrong because it was prescriptive. But if that's your criticism, then any science that's prescriptive, including ethics, must be rejected, in which case, you would have no normative or ethical basis on which to criticize the Nazi eugenicists. Consider our discussion of mathematics. You contend an individual who purposely adds 7 plus 5 and arrives at 11 performs an immoral act from the point of view of mathematics itself. I didn't say "immoral." An immoral act is a violation of a moral principle, not the violation of a mathematical one. The point I was making is that the concept of 'ought,' whether applied to mathematical reasoning or to moral reasoning presupposes a goal and pertains simply to the means of achieving that goal. But in such a case the "real" answer of 12 is obvious to almost all mathematicians. Now consider the "science" of eugenics as it existed in the early 20th century. Answers then were not so obvious. Neither was the "purpose" of critics. The intellectual atmosphere as a result took on the character of the Inquisition rather than legitimate scientific discourse. In such an atmosphere I don't see how anyone could think the concept of a "normative" science is a "good" one. But look what you're doing! You're criticizing normative science on normative grounds; you're saying that it's not a "good" one. "Good" and "bad" are normative concepts. The only way you can do that legitimately is if you have a rational, scientific basis for your criticism. Don't confuse "science" with physical science. Ethics can (and should) be scientific as well. By "scientific" I simply mean based on the facts of reality and validated by a process of reason. The science of ethics trumps all other sciences when it comes to prescribing human choices and actions, because the science of ethics IS the science of morality and moral values. A rational science of ethics would have condemned the Nazi's normative values. Even today many geneticists consider their science normative. They think their science has the mission of advocating the "improvement" of the human race which is "good" from the science's point of view. But "good" is not so easy to determine in the here and now. Ideas of "improvement" of the human race are bound to change in the next fifty to hundred years and there is the pesky problem of "unintended consequences" which means nothing more than "consequences resulting from imperfect knowledge of the "good." Therefore, I believe the human race would be far better of insisting that the science of modern genetics not be normative. Your argument is a two-edged sword. It could just as well be argued that if we don't make genetic alterations that appear warranted by today's standards, we'll regret it in the long run. Whether such alterations are justified or not can only be decided by weighing all of the relevant factors. They cannot be rejected a priori, simply on the grounds that human beings are fallible. In any case, it is up to the science of ethics to ascertain the propriety of genetic alterations in terms of human rights and human liberty.
I asked, "Furthermore, if there is no rational, scientific basis for a free society, then on what grounds do you object to what the Nazis did?" Humanism, Christianity, Liberalism, Utilitarianism...take your pick. I meant on what rational scientific grounds do you object to what the Nazis did? Recall that there was no "rational, scientific basis" for the "science" of eugenics on which the Nazis based and popularized their actions. What makes you think a "rational, scientific basis for a free society" would have headed the Nazis off? If it were sufficiently widespread and understood, it could have prevented the growth of Nazism to begin with. (See in this connection, Leonard Peikoff's book, The Ominous Parallels). But the point I was making is that without a rational, scientific ethics, you have no legitimate basis on which to oppose what the Nazis did. Do you get that?! When science loses its legitimacy as an unbiased source of knowledge it loses respect in the realm of political persuasion. Well, of course, there's good and bad science, just as there's good and bad economics. The fact that Keynesian economics is bad science doesn't discredit good economic science. The fact that a morality of self-sacrifice is bad ethics doesn't discredit a morality of rational self-interest. The fact that political philosophy has endorsed collectivism doesn't discredit a political philosophy of individualism.
I wrote, "Freedom is a good thing, because it leads to good consequences. If you agree with that, then what are we arguing about? Means. The integrity of science. Politics. Epistemology. Not ethics. We're not arguing about ethics, even though you're saying that we can't derive an 'ought' from an 'is,' and I'm saying that we can? Simultaneously and paradoxically, you agree that freedom is the means to our values and therefore that we ought to respect it. And where is our argument about politics? I thought we already agreed that freedom is a value and ought to be promoted.
I asked, "Where does she [Rand] "smuggle in" concepts, if you don't mind my asking? No, I don't mind, although you might not be satisfied with my reply since I don't have Rand's books readily at hand. [By the way, is there a source on the web that offers the text of Rand's writings which would make cutting and pasting convenient?] No, not her published works, for obvious reasons. They're still selling in bookstores and online. But I take it that you already have them. They're worth re-reading; the impression I have is that when you read them before, you didn't retain a lot of the ideas. It seems to me that Rand's entire argument hinges on the conflation of two meanings of the word "life." She proves that man cannot sustain his "life" without food, shelter and the material necessities of "life." Then, she contends that man must use his rationality to gain these material necessities of "life." Then, she concludes that man's "life" is not a proper "life" unless it is lived "qua man," i.e., rationally in every aspect. This is the leap of logic I don't buy. What leap of logic? Living the life of man "qua man" -- in a rational manner -- is the means of sustaining one's life. How do you obtain the material necessities of life -- the material values that your life requires -- without the exercise of reason in the production of necessary goods and services. Living life irrationally, on the other hand, is the path to its destruction. Yes, man requires certain material necessities to sustain his biological organism, but man (as I see it) has two means of gaining these material necessities: rationality, which could mean forming society, trading and the like, or animal brute force, which could mean simply taking what one requires from nature or other humans by brute force. The latter method has been shown repeatedly to be self-defeating. Predation destroys the incentive and ability of human beings to produce the values their lives require, which is why the standard of living is so low under coercive dictatorships and why so many people have died under these political systems. Moreover, if human beings have no right to the product of their effort, because others are justified in taking it by brute force, then they have no right to sustain their lives, in which case, they have no right to life. Brute force in the acquisition of values is not a rational method of human survival. This is one of the salient points in Rand's Atlas Shrugged and a principal theme of her philosophy, which you claim to be familiar with. Rand chooses the former, obviously, as more suited to man's proper life qua man, but this conclusion is her value judgment coming to the fore. But that value judgment isn't arbitrary; it's based on reason. Logic did not lead her inextricably to this conclusion from the premise that man needs food to live. Oh, yes it did! For man, the basic means of survival is reason. Man cannot survive, as animals do, by the guidance of mere percepts. A sensation of hunger will tell him that he needs food (if he has learned to identify it as "hunger"), but it will not tell him how to obtain his food and it will not tell him what food is good for him or poisonous. He cannot provide for his simplest physical needs without a process of thought. He needs a process of thought to discover how to plant and grow his food or how to make weapons for hunting. (Rand, "The Objectivist Ethics," in The Virtue of Selfishness, p. 21) In short, living life rationally is required in order to provide for man's basic needs as well as for all of the other values that make his life worth living. Only by conflating the two definitions of life, i.e., "life" as a biological function and "life" as a philosophical state of being, is Rand able to bridge the gap between "is" and "ought." You need to go back and read the relevant literature; your misunderstanding of Objectivism is showing. What is "life as a philosophical state of being"? This is certainly not a phrase that Rand or any other Objectivist has ever used. And I have no idea what it's supposed to mean.
I wrote, "Do you see how morality is itself simply a means to an end? That's the key point here. The normative nature of the principles of morality is no different, in this respect, from the normative nature of the rules of arithmetic. Both are prescriptive in the sense that both describe the means to a desired end." Once again you're conflating the two definitions of "wrong" in order to arrive at your conclusion. Yes, I agree morality is itself a means to an end, the end we should all seek to attain. But the "normative nature of the principles of morality" is essentially distinct from the "normative nature of the rules of arithmetic." I agree that there is an important distinction; I was simply showing in what way they're similar. This is the subject of our entire debate. You can't settle that debate by making a bald-faced assertion. What bald-faced assertion? You don't agree that both these subjects are normative in different ways? That's all I was saying. Arithmetic is a logical system deduced from an arbitrary premise. Oh, boy! No, it isn't! It's based on non-arbitrary facts of reality. For example, in a recent post I made the point, which you ignored, that the number 5 refers to the quantity | | | | |. That quantity is an observable fact. It is not arbitrary. We can get into a separate discussion of this, if you want, but I would recommend that you go back and read ITOE, if you haven't already done so. Insofar as the logic of arithmeticians is faithful to that premise, arithmetic considers their reasoning correct; insofar as it is not, arithmetic considers their reasoning incorrect. Arithmetic itself, qua science, goes no further than this. It makes no judgments of the purpose, motive or goal of the arithmetician. From the point of view of arithmetic, the calculations are either correct or incorrect...nothing more. From the point of view of REALITY, the calculations are either correct or incorrect. Mathematics is based on reality, not on arbitrary postulates. It is a fact of reality that | | plus | | equal | | | |. But I agree that mathematics is not ethics; I never said it was. On the other hand, principles of morality are a logical system of ethics deduced from a normative premise. The rules of logic still apply. Reasoning from this premise must be correct. However, morality itself, qua ethics, makes value judgments of the purpose, motives and goals of the actor. From the point of view of ethics, moral reasoning is either good or evil, right or wrong (in the moral sense). I think you place too much emphasis on deduction. Morality is largely inductive. Now you may claim the premise of certain principles of morality are not normative but objective (or intrinsic or realistic), but you must prove such a claim by means of argument, not by means of assertion. I thought I already did that by pointing out that happiness (and its corollary, a healthful state of life) is an ultimate value for human beings and that morality is a means to that end.
I wrote: "It [the "value" of "respecting each other's freedom"] can be observed by the methods of the social sciences like politics and economics.
I'd be interested in hearing you explain how it can be observed by the methods of these sciences. (You can't be talking about Austrian economics, because Austrian methods "observe" nothing. Austrian economics is pure deductive reasoning.) No, it isn't. It uses deduction, to be sure, but it isn't entirely deductive. Its principles are based on observable facts, such as those I pointed out in a previous post. I asked: "If that is the case, then I ask again, in the interests of an honest and fruitful discussion: 'What is the premise you assume to be objectively true from which you deduce the objectively true, moral ethic of "respecting each other's freedom?"' You answered: "The premise that without freedom, one is not free to pursue and achieve one's values."
I expected your reasoning to be tautological, but I did not expect your premise to be tautological. "...[W]ithout freedom, one is not free..." Yes, I suppose this is objectively true, but it is also meaningless. How is it meaningless to say that "without freedom, one is not free to pursue and achieve one's values"? I'm saying that achieving one's values is the goal, and freedom is the means. What's not to understand? Why not simply say: "Freedom is necessary to the pursuit and achievement of one's values?" If you like that better, fine; it means the same thing. The important point here is the content, not the form of expression. But that wouldn't be objectively true, unless we discount all of the world's socialists and the members of MoveOn.org. Yes, it would! Unless socialists and other statists are not free to pursue their values, they cannot achieve them. And they certainly can't expect their own freedom to be respected, if they're not willing to respect the freedom of others. The principle of freedom does not allow for double standards. One cannot claim the right to freedom of action, if one denies others that right.Bridging the "Is-Ought" gap is a pesky problem indeed! It's not a problem at all. I've given you repeated demonstrations of why morality is based on facts and why prescriptions are simply descriptions. And what have you done to refute my arguments? Nothing. Speaking of "assertions," all you've done is assert that one can't derive an 'ought' from an 'is' without bothering to criticize the arguments that I've already made showing that it can. Yes, the burden of proof is on me to prove my case. But I've met that burden; I've advanced an argument on behalf of my position. The burden now shifts to you. You must address my argument and show what's wrong with it, something you have yet to do.
- Bill (Edited by William Dwyer on 11/24, 10:56pm)
(Edited by William Dwyer on 11/24, 11:08pm)
|
|