About
Content
Store
Forum

Rebirth of Reason
War
People
Archives
Objectivism

Post to this threadMark all messages in this thread as readMark all messages in this thread as unreadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Page 7Page 8Page 9Forward one pageLast Page


Post 160

Wednesday, November 14, 2007 - 1:19pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Robert,

Only if you treat "rights" as a metaphysical absolute of nature -- something operating on a separate moral track from rational self-interest -- would you conclude that Israel (or any threatened entity) should wait to be clobbered before responding to the explicit threat of aggression.
A false dichotomy. You are saying that an absolute of nature is on a separate track from self-interest -- and that's a wrong way to think about the relation between nature and morality.

Ed


Post 161

Wednesday, November 14, 2007 - 1:25pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Mark,

... I don't view rights as a floating metaphysical essence disconnected from rational self interest and what is naturally good for man.
And neither do I. The false dichotomy of this postulated "disconnect" (between metaphysics and ethics), has allowed Robert B. to get a lot of unwarranted "mileage" in this debate. And I wish that I could have noted this fact sooner -- in order to save time and energy.

There's no disconnect between metaphysics and ethics.

Ed


Sanction: 9, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 9, No Sanction: 0
Post 162

Wednesday, November 14, 2007 - 5:47pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed says,

"You are saying that an absolute of nature is on a separate track from self-interest..."

Jesus.

No, I did not say that, Ed.

I said THE OPPOSITE.

Read my words.

Not YOUR words ABOUT my words.

MY words.

Ed, we have a problem more fundamental than your intrinsicism. I honestly don't think you can READ. Throughout this discussion, you have translated every single word I've said, in every post, through the filter of your preconceptions, reading in "meanings" that are simply not there, and simultaneously failing to acknowledge the existence of points I've made clearly and repeatedly. It's as if you are so busy thinking of your counter-arguments that you don't even pause to read the argument.

I haven't gotten that impression from anyone else in this discussion, even those who completely disagree with me. (Mark H, who similarly attributes to me views I don't hold, at least acknowledged that he hadn't bothered to read my posts before publicly mischaracterizing my positions.)

This is completely hopeless, and thus worthless.

Bye.

Sanction: 14, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 14, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 14, No Sanction: 0
Post 163

Wednesday, November 14, 2007 - 7:49pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
A summary, just so there will be no reasonable grounds for mistaking my meaning.

Contrary to Ed's claim, I do NOT claim that self-interest is incompatible with the factual "absolutes" of nature. I believe the OPPOSITE to be true.

However, I deny his smuggled-in premise: that concepts, such as "rights," are among those factual, metaphysically existing "absolutes" of nature.

In denying that concepts are facts of nature, I wish to stress that I am not denying the compatibility of self-interest with actual, concrete facts of nature.


Now, as a last stab at clarifying the confusion, please follow Rand through her own chain of definitions, which are available in the Lexicon. Here is the first chain of three interrelated definitions (I've underlined the key transitional words):

"A 'right' is a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man's freedom of action in a social context."

"A principle is 'a fundamental, primary, or general truth, on which other truths depend.'"

"Truth is the product of the recognition (i.e., identification) of the facts of reality."


Now, a second chain of definitions:

"A 'right' is a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man's freedom of action in a social context."

"...[A] principle is an abstraction which subsumes a great number of concretes."

"Abstractions as such do not exist; they are merely man's epistemological method of perceiving that which exists--and that which exists is concrete."


The meaning of either of these two chains couldn't be clearer:

For Rand, rights are principles; principles are truths; principles are also abstractions. Truths are human identifications of facts -- but not the facts themselves; abstractions are man's epistemological means of perceiving facts -- but not the facts themselves.

Or, simplified even further:

Rights = principles = truths = abstractions; but "abstractions as such do not exist." Therefore, the abstractions called rights "as such do not exist."

The belief that rights exist metaphysically, rather than only epistemologically, is what Rand referred to as intrinsicism, the fallacies of which she spelled out in ITOE -- specifically, in her discussion of Aristotelian "moderate realism," which she explicitly rejected.

If you wish to continue to argue that rights have a metaphysical status in nature, it's time to take up your argument with Rand.




Post 164

Thursday, November 15, 2007 - 3:32amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
"Cult-like secrecy" was a little bit of a hyperbole, but it was prompted by an exchange I had with an ARI member/writer. We corresponded biefly by email couple years ago, until finally I asked how he squared the position that the U.S. should intentionally kill innocent people in order to protect the country, with a philosophy that advocated individual rights (I have since heard the justification for this on RoR, but this was right after I started getting into the nitty gritty of Objectivism, and before I discovered RoR). Anyways, after my question, the correspondence came to a screeching halt, the response was that I should read more books about study Objectivism further. So that seemed fishy to me, is it "cult-like"? You can judge for yourself.

As for your second question, I have to run, so I can't pull up the specific quotes or articles, I will try later, but again, there was little hyperbole in my statement.

No, I do not believe it was moral to drop the A-bombs... you will have to wait till later to hear why!

-JF-


Post 165

Thursday, November 15, 2007 - 9:28amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jonathan:

No, I do not believe it was moral to drop the A-bombs... you will have to wait till later to hear why!


Before you do, please click here and read my post on my reasoning why it was moral to drop the A-bombs in Japan.

Post 166

Thursday, November 15, 2007 - 10:50amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jonathan,

The difference between Objectivism and the Austrian point of view, at least as I understand both, is that Rand created a complete philosophy, whereas Mises merely expanded a branch of economics. Objectivism is value-laden. Austrian economics is value-neutral. Rand's Objectivism fully articulates its ethics. Austrian economics has no ethical positions. Both are individualistic and free market oriented -- Objectivism because of its metaphysics ("primacy of existence") and ethics; Austrian economics because of its epistemological methodology, which is subjective and individualistic. While the Austrian methodology is individualistic, it has no metaphysical or ethical position on individualism.

Libertarians gravitate toward Austrian economics because it's methodology is in sync with libertarian philosophical principles, though Austrian economics is not a branch of libertarian philosophy. Objectivists like the outcomes of Austrian economics but generally have a hard time with its rationalist approach.

Regards,
Sherman


Post 167

Thursday, November 15, 2007 - 11:59amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Bill,

Now we're communicating...

You write:
We can identify that other people value happiness as an end in itself, by observing that they are members of the same species as we are. We can know that happiness is experienced by them as self-evidently valuable, just as it is experienced by us as self-evidently valuable. You're not disputing that, are you?
No. We can understand that other human beings seek to achieve ends in themselves (happiness) just as we do. However, I don't believe we can know that some of those valued ends are objectively or intrinsically "wrong" and some are objectively or intrinsically "right."

You write:
Well, without the freedom to act on your judgment, you can't act on your value judgments, right?
I can act on them, but I might not be able to achieve them. On the other hand, other individuals might be perfectly comfortable acting on their value judgments in a non-free environment simply because they hold different values than mine.

You write:
You can't "observe" it [the connection between "respecting each others' freedom" and "achieving our values"] in the sense that you can perceive it directly on a sensory-perceptual level, but you can certainly identify it by observing that certain conditions are required for man to achieve his values.
By saying "certain conditions are required for man to achieve his values" you are implying that all men necessarily (intrinsically?) have the same values. By saying you can "identify" the connection you are assuming that the connection exists and that the "certain conditions" you have in mind are required by all individuals to achieve their values.

I say no connection exists between a "right" to freedom and "achieving our values" because some of us may hold values (socialists and communists, for instance) which are not dependent on any "right" to freedom.

You write:
 I think that Rand and Mises were on the same page regarding the conditional nature of means and ends as they relate to human action, but Mises didn't go any further than that; Rand did. Rand identified that without the recognition of a 'right' to freedom of action, the choice to act on one's value judgments cannot be preserved. Now this may have been implicit in Mises, but it wasn't made explicit. Also, Mises didn't relate human values to man's biological needs -- to the fact that man is being of a specific nature, who requires certain objective conditions for the achievement of his happiness. Mises left it entirely subjective. According to the Austrians, no voluntary choice can be criticized, because values are subjective, but if values are subjective, then on what grounds do the Austrians criticize the subjective values of the socialists and interventionists? While advocating subjectivism, the Austrians smuggle objectivist ethics in the back door. This is also the problem with the economics profession in general. They approach economics as if it were a value-free science ('Wertfreiheit'), and disdain any attempt to 'moralize' about economic values. Galt forbid that an economist should ever endorse the "right" to the pursuit of happiness. Austrian economics could use a good dose of Objectivism! 
See my Post #166 to Jonathan. Based on it and your quote above I think we pretty much agree on the differences between Rand, Mises and their systems of thought. However, I must emphasize that Mises' economics were value-neutral although his political and philosophical leanings certainly were not. Mises was a classical liberal. He penned his political, social and philosophical preferences in a book called "Liberalism" in which he described a prototypical liberal society in which, I dare say, most Objectivists would feel comfortable living (and most libertarians would not, but that is another discussion).

Linking "human values to man's biological needs" is another point on which we disagree. I don't think such a link logically exists, but again that is another discussion.

You ask "on what grounds do the Austrians criticize the subjective values of the socialists and interventionists?" In my opinion, the beauty of Austrian economics is that it accepts the values of the socialists and interventionists as they state them and then criticizes the means (i.e., socialism and interventionism) they choose to achieve their stated values. Socialists and interventionists do not advocate socialism and interventionism as ends. They advocate socialism and interventionism as means to their ends, i.e., a chicken in every lunchbox and a roof over every head and the like. Austrian economics then sets out to prove by means of a value-neutral, logically consistent scientific method" that subjectivism and interventionism are unsatisfactory means of achieving the ends desired even when considered from the subjective point of view of the socialists and interventionists themselves.
 
It should be clear from this that Austrian economists do not "smuggle objectivist ethics in the back door." In fact, to do so would be counterproductive. For this reason I disagree that Austrian economics could use a "good dose of Objectivism." Why criticize an individual's ends when you can simply accept the ends as he states them and criticize the means he advocates to achieve his ends?

For instance, if you state you are in New York and your end is to be in Philadelphia and you say the shortest route to Philadelphia is via Los Angeles, why would I criticize your desire to be in Philadelphia? Why not simply accept your end desire to be in Philadelphia, as stated by you yourself (subjectivism) and then prove to you in a scientific, rational, logical, value-neutral manner that the route you suggested through Los Angeles is in reality not the shortest route to Philadelphia but one of the longest. In the process I could also point out the other consequences of choosing this roundabout means to achieve your stated ends which you might find unsatisfactory as well?

If socialists and interventionists want full bellies, accept their values but show them that socialism and interventionism are in reality not able to fill their bellies. Capitalism can and most efficiently to boot.
 
 


Sanction: 3, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 3, No Sanction: 0
Post 168

Thursday, November 15, 2007 - 3:47pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I wrote, "We can identify that other people value happiness as an end in itself, by observing that they are members of the same species as we are. We can know that happiness is experienced by them as self-evidently valuable, just as it is experienced by us as self-evidently valuable. You're not disputing that, are you?" Sherman replied,
No. We can understand that other human beings seek to achieve ends in themselves (happiness) just as we do. However, I don't believe we can know that some of those valued ends are objectively or intrinsically "wrong" and some are objectively or intrinsically "right."
Recall that, in an earlier post, I stated that there is no intrinsic value -- no end in itself -- that is morally right or wrong. (Of course, Objectivists use "intrinsic value" to refer to a value without a valuer instead of the way you're using it, as something that's valuable for its own sake.) So, I agree that one cannot morally prescribe ends, only means. But recall my statement that since everyone values happiness for its own sake (or as what you would call an "intrinsic value"), happiness "ought" to be recognized as our ultimate value. You don't disagree with that, do you? And since it is our ultimate value, the only question is, how do we achieve it -- by what means?

I wrote, "Well, without the freedom to act on your judgment, you can't act on your value judgments, right?"
I can act on them, but I might not be able to achieve them.
Come on! You're missing the point. By act on them, I meant choose them. You're not able to choose the actions that you value if you're not free to choose them.
On the other hand, other individuals might be perfectly comfortable acting on their value judgments in a non-free environment simply because they hold different values than mine.
They might be, but only if they're free to choose them, and in a society that does not recognize the right to freedom, their freedom exists only be default -- only by a role of the dice. If a different group gets into power with different values, they're out of luck. If they have no right to choose their values, then they have no right to life if someone in power wants them dead. They exist and function only by permission -- only at the behest of those who hold the power of life and death over them.

I wrote, "You can't "observe" it [the connection between "respecting each others' freedom" and "achieving our values"] in the sense that you can perceive it directly on a sensory-perceptual level, but you can certainly identify it by observing that certain conditions are required for man to achieve his values."
By saying "certain conditions are required for man to achieve his values" you are implying that all men necessarily (intrinsically?) have the same values.
We have to define our terms here. All human beings value happiness, and to that extent, have the same values. And freedom is certainly required for the pursuit of happiness. But if by "values," you are referring to what people act to gain and keep (Rand's definition), then freedom of action is required for that as well.
By saying you can "identify" the connection you are assuming that the connection exists and that the "certain conditions" you have in mind are required by all individuals to achieve their values.
That's right, and the connection does exist. The connection is freedom of action.
I say no connection exists between a "right" to freedom and "achieving our values" because some of us may hold values (socialists and communists, for instance) which are not dependent on any "right" to freedom.
Even a socialist or communist has to be free to choose his values; if he isn't free to choose them, he has no way to achieve them.

I wrote, "I think that Rand and Mises were on the same page regarding the conditional nature of means and ends as they relate to human action, but Mises didn't go any further than that; Rand did. Rand identified that without the recognition of a 'right' to freedom of action, the choice to act on one's value judgments cannot be preserved. Now this may have been implicit in Mises, but it wasn't made explicit. Also, Mises didn't relate human values to man's biological needs -- to the fact that man is being of a specific nature, who requires certain objective conditions for the achievement of his happiness. Mises left it entirely subjective. According to the Austrians, no voluntary choice can be criticized, because values are subjective, but if values are subjective, then on what grounds do the Austrians criticize the subjective values of the socialists and interventionists? While advocating subjectivism, the Austrians smuggle objectivist ethics in the back door. This is also the problem with the economics profession in general. They approach economics as if it were a value-free science ('Wertfreiheit'), and disdain any attempt to 'moralize' about economic values. Galt forbid that an economist should ever endorse the "right" to the pursuit of happiness. Austrian economics could use a good dose of Objectivism!"
See my Post #166 to Jonathan. Based on it and your quote above I think we pretty much agree on the differences between Rand, Mises and their systems of thought. However, I must emphasize that Mises' economics were value-neutral although his political and philosophical leanings certainly were not. Mises was a classical liberal. He penned his political, social and philosophical preferences in a book called "Liberalism" in which he described a prototypical liberal society in which, I dare say, most Objectivists would feel comfortable living (and most libertarians would not, but that is another discussion).
Why do you say that?
Linking "human values to man's biological needs" is another point on which we disagree. I don't think such a link logically exists, but again that is another discussion.
Sure it does. What do you think gives rise to values in the first place? We value happiness, because it is part of our biological nature to do so -- because we are wired in such a way biologically that pro-life actions contribute to our happiness and anti-life actions are inimical to it. Injury and illness cause pain and suffering; health and wellbeing produce pleasure and enjoyment.
You ask "on what grounds do the Austrians criticize the subjective values of the socialists and interventionists?" In my opinion, the beauty of Austrian economics is that it accepts the values of the socialists and interventionists as they state them and then criticizes the means (i.e., socialism and interventionism) they choose to achieve their stated values.
But the means are part of their values.
Socialists and interventionists do not advocate socialism and interventionism as ends. They advocate socialism and interventionism as means to their ends, i.e., a chicken in every lunchbox and a roof over every head and the like. Austrian economics then sets out to prove by means of a value-neutral, logically consistent scientific method" that subjectivism [socialism?] and interventionism are unsatisfactory means of achieving the ends desired even when considered from the subjective point of view of the socialists and interventionists themselves.
Okay, but then the Austrians are criticizing the values of the socialists and interventionists, are they not? This is not a value-neutral approach, whatever you may say about it.
It should be clear from this that Austrian economists do not "smuggle objectivist ethics in the back door."
By "smuggle objectivist ethics in the back door," I meant that by criticizing the political values of the socialists or interventionists, the Austrians are implicitly claiming that these values are objectively wrong -- even if only as means for achieving the desired ends.
In fact, to do so would be counterproductive.
Which is why their means are objectively wrong -- they don't in fact achieve the desired ends.
For this reason I disagree that Austrian economics could use a "good dose of Objectivism." Why criticize an individual's ends when you can simply accept the ends as he states them and criticize the means he advocates to achieve his ends?
Well, if the ends are bad (as means to more ultimate ends), then they deserve to be criticized, if only because you don't want bad ends to be achieved by any means.
For instance, if you state you are in New York and your end is to be in Philadelphia and you say the shortest route to Philadelphia is via Los Angeles, why would I criticize your desire to be in Philadelphia? Why not simply accept your end desire to be in Philadelphia, as stated by you yourself (subjectivism) and then prove to you in a scientific, rational, logical, value-neutral manner that the route you suggested through Los Angeles is in reality not the shortest route to Philadelphia but one of the longest. In the process I could also point out the other consequences of choosing this roundabout means to achieve your stated ends which you might find unsatisfactory as well?
Suppose that my end or goal were to murder your best friend and you found out that I was intent on stabbing him to death. Would you simply say, "Bill, using a knife is not going to work, because my best friend knows karate, and he'll disarm you before you get a chance to use it."? Or would you say, "Murdering my best friend is wrong -- i.e., not a proper goal, to begin with -- even if your means of achieving it is counterproductive."? Of course, you'd say the latter.

Now it is true that if we are talking about ultimate values, then you would employ an argument based on means, since you can't morally prescribe an ultimate value. (Recall my distinction between a moral 'ought' and an epistemological 'ought'.) So, according to Objectivism, since personal happiness is everyone's ultimate (or, in your words "intrinsic") value, human sacrifice (of self or others) is counterproductive, because it will result in the sacrifice of people's happiness.

- Bill

(Edited by William Dwyer on 11/15, 5:29pm)


Sanction: 3, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 3, No Sanction: 0
Post 169

Friday, November 16, 2007 - 3:49amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
The question at root is whether rights are real things (things existing in virtue of the kinds of beings that exist), or whether rights aren't real things (things only existing because of someone's "perception" or imagination).

Ed

p.s. And to say that something is "only" a concept doesn't work. Contrary to Kantian philosophy, proper concepts are always concepts of pre-existenting things.

(Edited by Ed Thompson on 11/16, 4:13am)


Post 170

Friday, November 16, 2007 - 9:30amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Contrary to Kantian philosophy, proper concepts are always concepts of pre-existenting things.


Ed,

That belief is probably at the root of your error on this subject. It isn't even true of many things that are not related to ethics or social issues.

The concept of a "concept" is one example.

The phenomenon of the perception of color is another. In this case, there certainly is (in the usual, non-hallucinatory case) something real, external and existing independently of the perceiver that is (partly) responsible for the perception of, say, red. Yet, it remains true that without a particular type of consciousness, perceiving in a certain way, the perception of red would not be what we commonly know it as. It is the form in which we experience certain facts. But we experience it in that form not only because of those external facts, but also because of facts about our perceptual mechanism.

[Note added in edit: It's true that the identity of our perceptual mechanism is not dependent on how or even whether we identify it, so this case has important differences to the case of rights. I'm only discussing here the epistemological issue raised by your statement.]

I recommend David Kelley's The Evidence of the Senses on this subject. It will help clarify for you the difference between intrinsic and objective.

It's true that consciousness is inherently relational, and hence concepts are concepts of something. But consciousness is not diaphanous (to use Kelley's phrase). (See ibid.)


(Edited by Jeff Perren on 11/16, 9:38am)


Post 171

Friday, November 16, 2007 - 12:13pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jeff,

You say that concepts can be about things that don't exist.

But that can't be true.

Ed


Post 172

Friday, November 16, 2007 - 1:09pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
No, that's not what I'm saying, but even here your statement isn't correct. 'Unicorn' and other concepts of that type are perfectly valid, even though they don't name something that exists (in the sense of being a real horse species with a real horn, etc).

But it doesn't look as if I'm going to make much progress by pressing the point, so I'm satisfied to leave the last word to you, if you wish.
(Edited by Jeff Perren on 11/16, 1:15pm)


Sanction: 8, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 8, No Sanction: 0
Post 173

Friday, November 16, 2007 - 1:45pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
First of all, let me apologize to Robert Bidinotto for not replying to his Post #102. I overlooked the fact that he had addressed some of his comments to me, and I should certainly have responded to him before now. But better late than never. He writes:
The conflation of the two senses of "wrong" -- i.e., "harmful/mistaken" with "immoral/evil" -- is actually a conflation of "objective" morality with the "intrinsic" morality. Objective moral judgments proceed from one's full context of knowledge: they depend on reason. Intrinsic moral evaluations, by contrast, "just are": certain ideas and actions are "good in themselves" or "evil in themselves."

I see this conflation of "objective" and "intrinsic" throughout this thread -- first, in the discussion of rights; now, in the discussion of morality. For example, in post #98, Bill writes:
"So, you acknowledge that slavery was wrong even before it was recognized as wrong. Would you say, then, that the wrongness of an action exists independently of man's recognition of it?"
In the sense of "harm" -- yes. In the sense of "immoral" -- no. Morality presupposes knowledge and free choice. If a person commits an act with no awareness that it is harmful, his action may be wrong in the sense of "mistaken," but not "wrong" in the moral sense.
So, Robert is accusing me of conflating an "intrinsic" theory of morality with an "objective" theory. What, according to Objectivism, is an intrinsic theory of morality? In her essay "What is Capitalism" in Capitalism, the Unknown Ideal, Rand writes:
There are, in essence, three schools of thought on the nature of the good: the intrinsic, the subjective, and the objective. The intrinsic theory holds that the good is inherent in certain things or actions as such, regardless of their context and consequences, regardless of any benefit or injury they may cause to the actors and subjects involved. It is a theory that divorces the concept of "good" from beneficiaries, and the concept of "value" from valuer and purpose -- claiming that the good is good in, by, and of itself. (p. 21)
Is this what I (or anyone else on this thread) has been advocating -- that the good is inherent in certain things or actions as such, regardless of their context and consequences, regardless of any benefit or injury they may cause to the actors and subjects involved? Of course, not!

Robert agrees that the wrongness of an action exists independently of man's recognition of it, if by "wrong," one means mistaken, but not if by "wrong" one means immoral, because morality presupposes knowledge and free choice. I agree that morality presupposes knowledge and free choice. For example, in order to be morally responsible for his action, a bank robber cannot commit his act at the behest of a hypnotist or because he was forced to by someone else. He must be aware that he is robbing the bank and he must freely choose the action.

Suppose, however, that he thinks that rich bankers are exploiting the poor and have no right to their ill-gotten gains. Suppose he fancies himself as a modern-day Robin Hood and thinks there's nothing morally wrong with his robbing a bank, even though he knows that he is harming the bank, its officers and employees. Does that mean there's nothing morally wrong with his action? Does his robbery only become morally wrong if he recognizes it as morally wrong; otherwise, it's simply a "mistake"? If anything, this view of morality should give one pause. If it were correct, one could not argue with the bank robber about the immorality of his action, because in order for him to acknowledge that his act is morally wrong, he would already have to believe that it's morally wrong.

Robert continues,
In another confusing formulation, Bill writes:
"To be sure, the wrongness of an action is identified by recognizing that it violates a moral principle, but that doesn't mean that its wrongness depends on that identification." [I meant it's moral wrongness.]
Here again, the dual senses of "wrongness" -- innocent harms versus intentional harms -- are confused.
Well, the bank robber is inflicting intentional harm; he just doesn't think it's morally wrong.
Certainly, an action may be "wrong" in the sense of being demonstrably harmful; no one is disputing that. But that "wrongness" is in a different category from the "wrongness" that violates a recognized moral principle.
I agree. My point was that the bank robber is acting immorally, despite his failure to recognize it. In fact, I would say that if one truly believes that an act is immoral, then one will not choose it. One has to believe that it is the right thing to do, in order to consider it worth doing. As I mentioned to Joe in a previous post, I understand the Objectivist distinction between errors of knowledge and errors of morality. However, I think that that distinction pertains to the difference between intentional acts and unintentional ones. If I shortchange someone unintentionally, that's an error knowledge. If I deliberately shortchange him, hoping that he won't notice, that's an error of morality, even if I don't think that shortchanging him is morally wrong.

In Post 163, Robert writes,
Rights = principles = truths = abstractions; but "abstractions as such do not exist." Therefore, the abstractions called rights "as such do not exist."

The belief that rights exist metaphysically, rather than only epistemologically, is what Rand referred to as intrinsicism, the fallacies of which she spelled out in ITOE -- specifically, in her discussion of Aristotelian "moderate realism," which she explicitly rejected.
Consider the proposition: "The earth revolves around the sun." Is that epistemological or metaphysical? It's epistemological, because it's a proposition, and propositions are epistemological. What about the fact that the earth revolves around the sun? Is that epistemological or metaphysical? Of course, it's metaphysical. The earth's revolution around the sun exists whether anyone recognizes it or not.

Now consider the principle that (within the proper social context) one ought to respect other people's freedom of action. Is that epistemological or metaphysical. Of course, it's epistemological, because it's a principle, and principles are epistemological. What about the fact that (within the proper social context) one ought to respect other people's freedom of action? Is that epistemological or metaphysical. It's metaphysical; like the earth's revolution around the sun, the obligation to respect the freedom of others exists whether anyone recognizes it or not.

So "a right" can refer to a principle of action -- a guide for making choices -- or it can refer to the moral obligation to make certain choices. Rand's definition of 'a right' as "a moral principle defining and sanctioning man's freedom of action in a social context" is an example of the first; her statement that "rights are conditions of existence required by man's nature for his proper survival" is an example of the second.

Joe has already made what I regarded as a valid criticism of Rand's second statement. He pointed out that freedom of action is a condition of existence required for a murderer's proper survival but that that doesn't mean that a murderer has a right to freedom of action. So how can 'rights' be conditions of existence required for man's proper survival?

Perhaps Rand would have responded to Joe's criticism by pointing out that in her statement about rights, she was referring not to criminals and other rights violators but to people who deserved to have their freedom respected. At any rate, insofar as she regards the second statement as a description (if not a definition) of rights, she would seem to be acknowledging that rights can be considered metaphysical in the sense that the conditions to which she refers exist independently of anyone's recognition.

So the debate that we've been having may simply be one in which we've been arguing at cross purposes by referring, on the one hand, to 'rights' as principles or guides to action, and on the other hand, to 'rights' as conditions of existence that ought to be respected for the sake of man's proper survival. If so, we are both correct, for rights can be either epistemological or metaphysical, depending on how one is using the term.

- Bill


(Edited by William Dwyer on 11/16, 1:47pm)


Post 174

Friday, November 16, 2007 - 4:07pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Bill,

Post 173 is dead on.

Ed


Sanction: 8, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 8, No Sanction: 0
Post 175

Friday, November 16, 2007 - 7:19pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I read the first several posts in this thread, and thought carefully about the implications of the ideas involved. Although I ran out of time, I came away with almost exactly the analysis presented by Bill Dwyer in post 173.

Then I read carefully Bob Bidinotto's post 163, in which he, step by step, presents quotations from Rand and systematically builds to his conclusion, namely that products of human thought,such as concepts, do not exist within the realm of metaphysics.

So, for example, in one quote Rand states..."Abstractions as such do not exist; they are merely man's epistemological method of perceiving that which exists--and that which exists is concrete."

However, my understanding of Rand's meaning doesn't quite accord with Bob Bidinotto's. When Rand says abstractions do not exist, she means except as products of human thinking. For "Metaphysics" refers to the nature of "essential reality". In one sense, a thinker might distinguish between essential reality, meaning everything that exists outside of man's consciousness; and, for lack of a better term, "non-essential reality" (or epistemology), which identifies the nature and means of man's consciousness. But this distinction, while valid, no longer applies if one substitutes for "metaphysics" the all-encompassing idea of "reality", which includes everything: natural requirements for human flourishing and moral principles, giraffes and the concept girrafe, existents and consciousness. From this perspective, a principle, or an abstraction, or arithmatic and calculus all absolutely exist. In other words the distinction between metaphysical and epistemological (or between essential and non-essential reality) is not ultimate; it is a strategic distinction that identifies different aspects of reality.

I am almost sure we all agree so far. Bob Bidinotto reasons that ethical/political principles are products of human consciousness, and so are excluded from "essential reality; and that this fact is integral to the ideas one is logically led to believe about the nature and content of those principles. And he is right, of course, that religious intricism leads to a certain way of looking at man and moral principles, such as opposition to all abortions, regardless of term. So does epistemological confusion associated with religion, such as "the beginning of wisdom is fear of the lord."

But what B's reasoning apparently overlooks is that one can avoid intricism but dispute his ideas about the nature of moral principles. For when one recognizes the valid distinction between metaphysical reality and epistemology, and then applies this distinction to individual rights, so that rights are seen as products of human thought that accurately describe aspects of metaphysical reality, one can, within this framework, prove that moral principles are logically inferred from human nature. Where's the intricism?

Now, I readily admit that my understanding about this subject is far from complete. I'll have to read The Evidence of the Senses. Perhaps there is some distinction that I'll grasp that I am missing now. But for the life of me, I can't see B's point as sound, based on my understandng.

To Jeff, I agree that concepts can refer to unreal imaginary constructs, such as woodland nymphets or Mises' "Evenly Rotating Economy". But I don't see how this bears on what I wrote above.

I am dying to write something about the relationship between Rand's Aristotelian value laden world view, and Mises' allegedly value-free positivism. With a few non-essential adjustments, Austrain economics merges perfectly with objectivism. George Reisman, and even Rand-hater Murray Rothbard before him, have explained this clearly. Economics is actually a branch of the philosophy of ethics, dealing with the conditions required, both economic and political, for the production and acquisition of material abundance--a moral value.


Post 176

Saturday, November 17, 2007 - 5:18amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Wow, Mark.

Excellent analysis.

Ed


Sanction: 5, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 5, No Sanction: 0
Post 177

Saturday, November 17, 2007 - 5:39amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Bill Dwyer wrote:

So the debate that we've been having may simply be one in which we've been arguing at cross purposes by referring, on the one hand, to 'rights' as principles or guides to action, and on the other hand, to 'rights' as conditions of existence that ought to be respected for the sake of man's proper survival. If so, we are both correct, for rights can be either epistemological or metaphysical, depending on how one is using the term.
It seemed to me the arguments were at cross purposes from the start. I partly agree with your distinction, but will express it differently. I took the Bidinotto or Rowlands position as being about what rights are in the political realm (or social context) and yours to be about the basis (or source) of rights in the political realm. I put it this way because principles or guides to action apply in either position.

A couple quotes from Rand may help clarify my point.
"Rights" are a moral concept -- the concept that provides a logical transition from the principles guiding an individual's actions to the principles guiding his relationship with others -- the concept that preserves and protects individual morality in a social context -- the link between the moral code of a man and the legal code of a society, between ethics and politics. Individual rights are the means of subordinating society to moral law (Man's Rights).
The phrases "principles guiding an individual's actions" and "the moral code of a man" are about the source.
The source of man's rights is not divine law or congressional law, but the law of identity. A is A -- and Man is Man. Rights are conditions of existence required by man's nature for his proper survival. If man is to live on earth, it is right for him to use his mind, it is right to act on his own free judgment, it is right to work for his values and to keep the product of his work (Man's Rights and Atlas Shrugged).
The last sentence is about what the source is. There is also a pretty clear distinction here between what rights are and their source, the same one I made. To make a case for the source of rights does not make one an "intrinsicist" in the pejorative sense. (But it would if the source were said to be divine commands.)

(Edited by Merlin Jetton on 11/17, 7:41am)


Post 178

Saturday, November 17, 2007 - 7:06amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
After all of this excellent analysis by Bill, Merlin, and Mark -- it can be said that rights can be thought of epistemologically, but that they are metaphysically-grounded none-the-less.

Ed


Post 179

Saturday, November 17, 2007 - 8:00amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Bill,

I think our discussion is derailed because I am thinking from the point of view of an Austrian economist and you are thinking from the point of view of an Objectivist philosopher. As a consequence, I resist any attempt on your part to assign judgments of absolute (objective) value to an individual’s ends. You, on the other hand, endeavor to tie an individual’s ends to some "ultimate" end or "ultimate" value that is common to all individuals in the human race, thus making it an objective end or an objective value for all human beings. Perhaps this is typical of discussions between scientists and philosophers. (Not that I’m arrogant enough to consider myself a "scientist." I use the general terms only for purposes of illustration.)

I have definite views with regard to which of all possible ends should be sought after by each individual human being. However, I regard these views as philosophic, not economic. Let me explain by analogy.

A nuclear scientist does not allow "value" or "morality" or "ethics" to color the physics of his making an atomic bomb. He impartially, dispassionately and amorally goes about his work, following wherever the science leads him. To act with moral prejudice might close off possible avenues of scientific success or lead him astray.

On the other hand this same nuclear scientist can remove his physicist’s hat, don his philosopher’s cap and make moral, value judgments about whether or not the fruit of his scientific labor is right or wrong, good or bad. This philosophic judgment may cause him to discontinue his work on atomic bombs, but it cannot in anyway affect the science of making atomic bombs.

The philosopher in you writes: "All human beings value happiness, and to that extent, have the same values." The economist in me responds: "All human beings value the idea of happiness as a general concept, but the particulars that comprise the idea of happiness vary for each individual person. Thus, there is no possible way all persons share the same particular values."

The philosopher in you writes: "We value happiness, because it is part of our biological nature to do so -- because we are wired in such a way biologically that pro-life actions contribute to our happiness and anti-life actions are inimical to it. Injury and illness cause pain and suffering; health and wellbeing produce pleasure and enjoyment." The economist in me responds: "We value happiness because it is part of our human nature to do so. Yes, we are biologically hardwired to feel pain and suffering, pleasure and enjoyment, but these physical sensations do not directly correspond to or are inimical to our happiness. Many individuals choose painful means to achieve their end of happiness, a football player, for example, or a saintly martyr."

The philosopher in you writes: "I meant that by criticizing the political values of the socialists or interventionists, the Austrians are implicitly claiming that these values are objectively wrong -- even if only as means for achieving the desired ends." The economist in me responds: "By criticizing the means advocated by socialists or interventionists, Austrian economists are saying directly that these means are objectively incapable of achieving the ends sought when considered from the point of view of those seeking those ends. The Austrians are simply stating that the means chosen are incompatible with the end sought, just as straw inside a rubber balloon is incompatible with the end of building an atomic bomb. In no way, either directly or implicitly, does such a "scientific" statement imply that these means are wrong in an objectively moral sense.

The philosopher in you offers your scenario of knifing my best friend and suggests my obvious response should be to dissuade you by arguing that murder is wrong. The economist in me responds that your scenario is philosophic in nature, not economic. By using the term "murder" you have charged the scenario with social and moral values, removing it from the realm of economic discussion. An economist’s scenario would have used the term "kill."

And so it goes and never the twain shall meet?

Regards,
Sherman

P.S. You asked why I thought most libertarians would be uncomfortable living in a classical liberal world. I think most libertarians nowadays are so vehemently anti-government that the very idea of living under a government becomes uncomfortable.








(Edited by Sherman Broder on 11/17, 8:02am)

(Edited by Sherman Broder on 11/17, 8:03am)


Post to this threadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Page 7Page 8Page 9Forward one pageLast Page


User ID Password or create a free account.