About
Content
Store
Forum

Rebirth of Reason
War
People
Archives
Objectivism

Post to this threadMark all messages in this thread as readMark all messages in this thread as unreadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Page 7Page 8Page 9Forward one pageLast Page


Post 180

Tuesday, May 24, 2005 - 9:06amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Daniel,

Yes and yes.

Sheesh! I mean, can't a guy attempt a little philosophical trail-blazing, from time to time?

Is it too much to ask to let a guy practice a little selective recovery of the "babies" (from different philosophical tubs)--a little selective omission of the dirty bathwater (sloshing around in past philosopher's heads)?

Otherwise, what've we got here--but "guild philosophism"? [another term that ought to escape Wikipedia's enormous, encroaching, encompassment of everything else]
-----------------

The beef you had last year is now rotten ...
Daniel, your main concern last year was the quality of my account of intent (the intentional nature consciousness).

Now, I had felt I'd done the concept justice--though perhaps not enough justice to please all rational onlookers. Daniel, does my previously-defended position still appear deficient--on the matter of accounting for intent?

I'm willing to at least enter into a comparative analysis of my new view--with those of mainstream superstars (Dennett & Co; Popper et al; James et tu; Jung & the rest; etc. ad infinitum)

Ed

Post 181

Tuesday, May 24, 2005 - 3:16pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed:

Now, I had felt I'd done the concept justice--though perhaps not enough justice to please all rational onlookers. Daniel, does my previously-defended position still appear deficient--on the matter of accounting for intent?

I'm willing to at least enter into a comparative analysis of my new view--with those of mainstream superstars (Dennett & Co; Popper et al; James et tu; Jung & the rest; etc. ad infinitum)
Sounds like grist for a new thread. If you do, a brief restatement of the issue for newcomers such as myself would be nice.

NH


Post 182

Tuesday, May 24, 2005 - 7:56pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Nathan, my recent "Veridicality" essay actually has a predecessor--one that had caused some strife. Here is the link to the original thread:

http://solohq.com/Forum/GeneralForum/0170.shtml#0

Ed


Post 183

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 1:23amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed:
Nathan, my recent "Veridicality" essay actually has a predecessor--one that had caused some strife. Here is the link to the original thread:

http://solohq.com/Forum/GeneralForum/0170.shtml#0




Strife-schmife!

If philosophy doesn't stir people up, then we're just serving milquetoast.

I checked the thread. Under twenty rather tame posts, Ed. To what strife are you referring?

(My exchange with Abolaji became a bit hotter than that before I took it to emails.)

Probably just as well we don't do a thread, though. I admittedly skimmed your piece, but I suspect that my approach to this subject will be different from yours, and I'm not ready to debate it yet.

Nathan


Post 184

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 8:48amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Nathan, very well--more serious debate of this "old" work of mine can wait.

Hell, it may even be best to wait. It is my belief that the thing came out before its time (not enough fleshing out of the underlying similarity to what it is that we call objectivism).

Ed

Post 185

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 11:23amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Hi Ed,

Not sure if this is the appropriate place for it, but I don't think your "veridicality of conceptual discernment" escapes Hume's problem of induction. As I got to understand it, I realized that lots of other philosophers have offered similar solutions (including me). I'll explain by responding to one of your examples you put out there in the other thread:

Canada-North-of-Mexico. Hume will argue that we can at least conceive of all the land just above the US breaking off from the US and shifting to a new position down around South America. We could keep referring to that land as Canada, or if we insist that north-of-Mexico is a necessary characterstic of Canada, then we'd simply stop referring to the thing that shifted to that new position as Canada, for necessity dictates that it would've ceased to be Canada at least as soon as it stopped being north of Mexico.

Whether we categorize that land Canada doesn't help us escape the problem of induction. The problem is that we don't know whether that land can change position w/r/t Mexico. 

A big conclusion drawn from Hume is that categorical certainty doesn't lead to predictive certainty. If you're not convinced, it might help us to go back to the popular Raven Paradox.

Jordan


Post 186

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 12:02pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jordan:
Not sure if this is the appropriate place for it, but I don't think your "veridicality of conceptual discernment" escapes Hume's problem of induction. As I got to understand it, I realized that lots of other philosophers have offered similar solutions (including me). I'll explain by responding to one of your examples you put out there in the other thread:

Canada-North-of-Mexico. Hume will argue that we can at least conceive of all the land just above the US breaking off from the US and shifting to a new position down around South America. We could keep referring to that land as Canada, or if we insist that north-of-Mexico is a necessary characterstic of Canada, then we'd simply stop referring to the thing that shifted to that new position as Canada, for necessity dictates that it would've ceased to be Canada at least as soon as it stopped being north of Mexico.

Whether we categorize that land Canada doesn't help us escape the problem of induction. The problem is that we don't know whether that land can change position w/r/t Mexico. 

A big conclusion drawn from Hume is that categorical certainty doesn't lead to predictive certainty. If you're not convinced, it might help us to go back to the popular Raven Paradox.

In addition, I don't recall Ed ever actually addressing this issue: Is 'knowledge' only that which we have personally corroborated?
 
He didn't like the idea of calling information we derive from encyclopedias knowledge, but has he personally verified that Canada is north of the US? That astronauts have walked on the moon? That the moon is a quarter-million miles from Earth?
 
This is an aspect of the problem of induction. It is unlikely in the extreme that the US faked the moon landings, but that is exactly the definition of inductive logic: likely but not absolutely certain.
 
Excluding this from what we call knowledge would exclude the vast majority of human belief, I think.
 
Nathan Hawking
 
 
 


Post 187

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 1:55pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jordan,

Whether we categorize that land Canada doesn't help us escape the problem of induction. The problem is that we don't know whether that land can change position w/r/t Mexico. 

A big conclusion drawn from Hume is that categorical certainty doesn't lead to predictive certainty. If you're not convinced, it might help us to go back to the popular Raven Paradox.
On the contrary, noncontradictory categorization SIDESTEPS the problem of induction, as it has been laid out (it renders it a non-problem; or pseudo-issue). The "problem"--as it has been outlined--is analogous to the "problem" of platonic idealism (these "problems" stem from more basic, though false, premises).

"Induction-by-mechanistic-understanding" is a term that offers an advancement of insight from the older, limited perspective of Hume's "Induction-by-mere-enumeration." It is my contention that this advancement in perspective ought to compel rational agents to adopt the superior term.

To put a fine point on it, your statement:

The problem is that we don't know whether that land can change position w/r/t Mexico.
 ... reflects an error in basic premises. You see, we DO know whether that land can change position--because we have a mechanistic understanding of contintental drift and plate tectonics. Merely framing the question, as you have, under a "veil of ignorance" does not create a real problem--it merely creates the appearance of a problem (a "problem" that is transcended by overcoming the limitations of the veiled perspective).

A big conclusion drawn from Hume is that categorical certainty doesn't lead to predictive certainty.
"[P]redictive certainty" is a condition of omniscience, something meta-contextual--but this is another non-problem (there is no such thing as veridical foresight/foreknowledge--it serves no rational standard). I, in contrast, don't consider discovery of this human lack of omniscience--a "big conclusion." This "problem of non-omniscience," just like before, phrases the question in a veiled, paradoxical manner (ie. uses a mere hypothetical limitation of human understanding)--rather than in a more actualized way (not knowing "everything"--does not entail not knowing "anything").

Ed


Post 188

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 2:09pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Nathan,

In addition, I don't recall Ed ever actually addressing this issue: Is 'knowledge' only that which we have personally corroborated?
No.
 

He didn't like the idea of calling information we derive from encyclopedias knowledge, but has he personally verified that Canada is north of the US? That astronauts have walked on the moon? That the moon is a quarter-million miles from Earth?
No.

 

This is an aspect of the problem of induction. It is unlikely in the extreme that the US faked the moon landings, but that is exactly the definition of inductive logic: likely but not absolutely certain.
The moon landing (a past event whose context is now unavailable for direct access) will have to be viewed as a merely the best available opinion--one that is strengthened / weakened by the level of consilience surrounding it.

 

Excluding this from what we call knowledge would exclude the vast majority of human belief, I think.
I don't share your concern, Nathan. Look at contemporary ethics / politics--and tell me, what do you see? A vast majority of erroneous belief. This is no problem, as we are merely in the matrix--and we need to take the red pill. I am (among many others here) manufacturing red pills.

Ed


Post 189

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 2:49pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Hi Ed,

We might find that every time we check the mechanics of continental drift and plate tectonics that they are the same. But how do we know that next time they won't be different? That's the problem of induction.

I suspect you'll want to side-step the problem by saying that, well, if the mechanics turn out to be different the next time we check, then it's a new thing altogether that we're observing, not plate tectonics or continental drift.

And to be sure, we needn't limit ourselves to continental drift and plate tectonics when outlining conceivable ways in which Canada could wind up being not north of Mexico. Canada could also get destroyed by a big asteroid, making it not north of anything. Or the asteroid could smash it and push it down just south of Mexico. Or maybe gravity could screw up and let Canada fly out into space. Or maybe the electromagnetic force could screw up and let Canada sink into the center of the Earth. 

Again, these ideas are totally absurd and unreasonable, but they're not (using traditional philosophical jargon) logically invalid. Yes, these "maybe X could happen" examples are structured under a "veil of ignorance" (i.e., under non-omniscience), but no, I don't see that your view escapes Hume's problem.

Jordan

(Edited by Jordan on 5/25, 3:10pm)

(Edited by Jordan on 5/25, 3:11pm)


Post 190

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 3:01pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed: “Induction-by-mechanistic-understanding" is a term that offers an advancement of insight from the older, limited perspective of Hume's "Induction-by-mere-enumeration." It is my contention that this advancement in perspective ought to compel rational agents to adopt the superior term.”

It might do, Ed, if you could put together an argument for this superior term. So far, you’ve given us an example, the star-shaped cookie cutter, viz: “If you've made a cookie cutter into the shape of a star, then you may logically assume that the cookies cut (all of the cookies cut) with this cookie cutter--will come out star-shaped.”

Induction is usually understood as the process of drawing general empirical truths from particular facts. The particular fact in the above case seems to be: “this cookie cutter is star-shaped”; the inductive generalisation: “all of the cookies cut with this cookie cutter will come out star-shaped”.

As it stands, this is a non sequitur. In order to show that star-shaped cookie cutters invariably produce star-shaped cookies, you need a connecting principle. Presumably, this principle is “appeal to mechanistic understanding”. So now you’ve got an argument: 1) this cookie cutter is star-shaped; 2) mechanistic understanding of the action of cutters and dough; 3) all of the cookies cut will be star-shaped.

I don’t think we’d have any problem agreeing over what is meant by (1) and (3), but what about (2)? How would you establish the principle of mechanistic understanding? You can’t re-use the cookie cutter argument as I’ve outlined it, because that argument appeals to the principle without establishing it. So how would you arrive at the principle of mechanistic understanding without begging the question?

Brendan


Post 191

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 3:10pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jordan, try this teaser on for size (it resembles Matson's veridical generalization about all helium atoms; making his induction necessarily true--true by definition--by valid expansion of a previously-limited definition):

the fully explicit definition of human will be:
  • Human =df rational sensitive animate material substance
This is obtained from the compressed definition above by successively replacing each definable term (definiendum) in the definition with its definiens. Thus, we replace ‘animal’ in ‘human =df rational animal’ with its definiens and obtain ‘human =df rational sensitive living thing’. We then do the same for the definiendum ‘living thing’ to get ‘human =df rational sensitive animate body’, and finally, replacing ‘body’ with its definiens ‘material substance’ we obtain the fully explicit definition above. A glance at the Tree of Porphyry shows that the complete definition of a species consists of its differentia together with the differentiae of all of the genera under which it falls.
source:
http://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/433/PorphyryTree.html

Again (for emphasis):
... the complete definition of a species consists of its differentia together with the differentiae of all of the genera under which it falls.
The valid categorical certainties in the Tree of Porphyry say something about the knowable reality we inhabit--we just need to keep ALL of the valid categoricals in mind (and not just the hyper-clear and evident ones of this Tree)--while avoiding contradictions--when examining particulars (in order to get to the general).

p.s. The Raven Paradox is a pseudo-problem that will be solved at the genomic level, rather than by armchair ontological stipulation. From my view, it's a science question merely masquerading as a philosophical one. It will become solved after understanding the "mechanism" that atrributes the property of blackness to ravens.

Ed


Post 192

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 3:37pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

Your example deals with categorization, not with prediction, so it doesn't escape the problem of induction. Take the Raven Paradox. We see one raven, then another, then another, and we find that they're all black, so we conclude that all ravens are black. This implies that blackness is a necessary characteristic of ravens, which further implies that every non-black thing will also be a non-raven. This doesn't tell us anything knew; it just explores the bounds of the category.

But how do we know that there are no grey ravens? I suspect you'd say: because blackness is essential to that which we refer to as a raven. That is, even if you saw a grey bird with genes the same as a black raven, then you'd still say the grey bird is not a raven. Which is fine; it just doesn't escape the problem of induction because simply restating/retaining the category is deductive. All it does is make us pop out a new category: one for grey birds that are genetically the same as ravens. Of course, you might now want to say that blackness is not necessary for ravens, in which case you could allow the grey bird into the raven category. But then we'd be uncertain as to whether future ravens could be grey, which of course, is the problem of induction

Jordan


Sanction: 3, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 3, No Sanction: 0
Post 193

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 3:43pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jordan,
You still haven't grasped that 'essentiality' is epistemelogical, not metaphysical. Re-read IOE. Re-read again.
Re-read Piekoff's Analytic-Synthetic Dichotomy. Re-read again.  Loop as needed.


Post 194

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 3:46pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed:

In addition, I don't recall Ed ever actually addressing this issue: Is 'knowledge' only that which we have personally corroborated?
No.
 

I agree, but do we not then have to allow for "knowledge" which is less than certain? 


He didn't like the idea of calling information we derive from encyclopedias knowledge, but has he personally verified that Canada is north of the US? That astronauts have walked on the moon? That the moon is a quarter-million miles from Earth?
No.
I thought not.

This is an aspect of the problem of induction. It is unlikely in the extreme that the US faked the moon landings, but that is exactly the definition of inductive logic: likely but not absolutely certain.
The moon landing (a past event whose context is now unavailable for direct access) will have to be viewed as a merely the best available opinion--one that is strengthened / weakened by the level of consilience surrounding it. 
 
In principle, then, this includes almost all historical statements. Are you now allowing that "knowledge" might include DEGREES of certitude?  


Excluding this from what we call knowledge would exclude the vast majority of human belief, I think.
I don't share your concern, Nathan. Look at contemporary ethics / politics--and tell me, what do you see? A vast majority of erroneous belief. This is no problem, as we are merely in the matrix--and we need to take the red pill. I am (among many others here) manufacturing red pills.

But are you? That's just another way of saying "What I say is true!" Perhaps you are taking blue pills and are simply colorblind.

Pointing to the vast body of erroneous belief does not establish your own view of what constitutes knowledge. My point was that if absolute certitude is required, most of what we ordinarily think of as knowledge goes out the window--whatever the color of the pill we WISH to take.

Jordan's line of questioning about induction is a good one.
 
You seem to be claiming that the problem of induction disappears if we apply the right DEDUCTIVE methods to it.

Is that a fair encapsulated assessment of your position?

Nathan Hawking


Post 195

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 12:47pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I wrote:
>>Um, Ed, is this "induction by mechanistic understanding" something you've come up with yourself?...kinda like your other idea that via experience, knowledge moves into "the a priori zone"?

Ed replied:
>Yes and yes.Sheesh! I mean, can't a guy attempt a little philosophical trail-blazing, from time to time?

Of course! And it is clear you are a fellow of considerable intellectual enthusiasm, which is a very good thing.

The reason I ask tho is that the two problems are connected.

Your "a priori zone" theory, where knowledge moves to after experience, seems to be a reply to Kant. However, it involves a basic misunderstanding, in that the whole meaning of "a priori" wrt Kant is that it is knowledge *prior* to, not after, experience - and that includes *any* experience by *any* human at *any* time. So obviously despite your intentions, your theory does not reply to Kant.

As Kant was replying to Hume, I suggest that by extension your reply to Hume may involve a similar misunderstanding.

If I may guess where the misunderstanding lies based on your analogy, it is as follows: induction is not a question of making a "cookie cutter", and then applying it to certain situations to see if they come out star shaped - you already know they will! If anything, this analogy relates more closely to formal logic. An inductive process would be more like *observing a number of star shaped cookies* and then on that basis predicting that more star shaped cookies will continue to appear in future.

As to Hume, what Jordan sez is right.

Nathan:
>This is an aspect of the problem of induction. It is unlikely in the extreme that the US faked the moon landings, but that is exactly the definition of inductive logic: likely but not absolutely certain.

Nathan, Hume's result applies not only to *absolutely certain* but to *likely* or *probable* too.

- Daniel

Post 196

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 7:16pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Daniel:

Nathan:

>This is an aspect of the problem of induction. It is unlikely in the extreme that the US faked the moon landings, but that is exactly the definition of inductive logic: likely but not absolutely certain.

 

Nathan, Hume's result applies not only to *absolutely certain* but to *likely* or *probable* too.

 

Which result? Applies how?

Are you saying that things cannot be known (using induction) with ANY degree of certainty or likeliness?

NH


Post 197

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 8:18pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed:

the fully explicit definition of human will be:
  • Human =df rational sensitive animate material substance
This is obtained from the compressed definition above by successively replacing each definable term (definiendum) in the definition with its definiens. Thus, we replace ‘animal’ in ‘human =df rational animal’ with its definiens and obtain ‘human =df rational sensitive living thing’. We then do the same for the definiendum ‘living thing’ to get ‘human =df rational sensitive animate body’, and finally, replacing ‘body’ with its definiens ‘material substance’ we obtain the fully explicit definition above. A glance at the Tree of Porphyry shows that the complete definition of a species consists of its differentia together with the differentiae of all of the genera under which it falls.
source:
http://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/433/PorphyryTree.html

Again (for emphasis):

 
 
This sort of tree, and its verbal equivalent, is invariably seductive to some. Unfortunately it is also often USELESS in the real world.

For example, it defines "animal" as composed of two categories--rational and irrational. Then, of course, it neatly tucks human under rational, and beasts under irrational.

A wave of the hand, a twirl of the magic baton, a viola! the problem is solved.

Ooops! One little snag. Some nonhumans are more rational than some humans.

"Rationality," it turns out, is NOT a defining characteristic.
 
How many will read that, shrug, and come back to repeat the same formula for defining humans next week? More than one, I fear.
... the complete definition of a species consists of its differentia together with the differentiae of all of the genera under which it falls.
Nice-sounding words.

PROBLEM: Now tell us, without referring to lineage, which differentia make one being a pan and another a homo sapiens?
  • Rationality? Chimps are rational.
  • Bipedalism? Chimps can use their feet alone, and some people are born without them.
  • Anatomy? Some human are born with unusual anatomy.
  • Speech? Chimps are as capable as many humans who use sign language.
If you cannot, that should be sending you a signal that your concept-formation by classification has some serious defects and/or limitations.
The valid categorical certainties in the Tree of Porphyry say something about the knowable reality we inhabit--we just need to keep ALL of the valid categoricals in mind (and not just the hyper-clear and evident ones of this Tree)--while avoiding contradictions--when examining particulars (in order to get to the general).
If you can show me how what you just said actually SOLVES the problem I posed above, I'll be impressed. I keep hearing people say "we just need to" do this or that for identificatory problems like this, but they never seem to get around to a demonstration.

Hand-waving and bluffing doesn't count.
p.s. The Raven Paradox is a pseudo-problem that will be solved at the genomic level, rather than by armchair ontological stipulation.
Ah, that will doubtless be your out for the chimp/human problem I posed. "They have different genes." 

But that's a cop-out. That's why I excluded heredity. It's a dodge because you are NOT using a genetic tree for classification. You are using a tree of alleged physical/mental "differentia," a form of essentialism.

It fails because there is no "essense of chimp" to compare with an "essense of human." It would probably fail even more spectacularly if we compared modern humans to Neanderthals, apparently a different species but even more like us than chimpanzees.

As I say, when someone can ACTUALLY do the defining they keep claiming is possible, I'll be impressed.
From my view, it's a science question merely masquerading as a philosophical one. It will become solved after understanding the "mechanism" that atrributes the property of blackness to ravens.
Then you don't understand the problem. As usually stated, it involves more than ravens.

I don't actually regard the problem as all that difficult, but it is NOT solved by discovering the genetic cause of raven blackness. If that were true, then an albino raven would not actually be a raven even though descended from raven parentage.

Nathan Hawking


Post 198

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 8:28pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jordan

I don't see that your view escapes Hume's problem.
My view never suffered from Hume's problem (it sidesteps enumeration and jumps to mechanistic understanding). Hume's problem stems from the basic error of viewing a mind as having merely perceptive powers of awareness--ie. no conceptual powers. Several self-quotes will make this point more clear:

Classical conceptualists start in the quicksand of "paddlehack" my euphemism for the acronym PDLHK (Plato-Descartes-Locke-Hume-Kant). This quicksand drowns you more the more that you wrestle around in it. How can this be?

Their shared error is in thinking that the mind's "ideas" [regard "ideas" as "concepts" - for the best view of this fundamental error!] are that OF WHICH we are directly conscious (instead of them being that BY WHICH we are conscious). This confuses "thought" with "things" and "mode of cognition" with "content of cognition," ultimately placing a burden on the classical conceptualist to defend that "the names we use derive their significance from the ideas in our minds to which they refer" (the Innate Idea Problem).

But if "ideas" are merely that BY WHICH we attain conceptual consciousness of really existing things (that BY WHICH we understand what is common to some particulars - and in meaningful contrast to others) then, with regard to any commonality that we do come to understand in this way, we can affirm rather than "deny its objective reality."
and ...

Locke's insufficient understanding is found in his inability - without explicit acknowledgement of intellectual powers - to account for general (abstract) ideas. To his credit, he does acknowledge the existence of these ideas, but does not explain how they can get into our heads.

And merely interjecting the word "understanding" does not exonerate him if human understandings are left unexplained due to his failure to explicitly acknowledge the powers of the intellect (intellectual understanding).

The theme running through PDLHK is that the mind is entirely a sensitive faculty (no intellectual understanding). In this respect, besides the immediate perceptions of sense-experience, we can only be conscious OF the ideas in our minds (as if we are "sensing" all of what's in our heads - without an understanding of how things got there or, what is the other side of the intellect-free coin, what their purpose is).

On this deficiency of Locke - that of failing to account for how abstract ideas, which are taken to be THAT WHICH we are directly conscious of - can get into the mind (which is assumed to be entirely a sensitive faculty) Hume takes Locke to task, attacking the inconsistency.

For illustrative purposes, read this quote from Hume, and view it from his perspective (that the mind is a sensing organ; without any explicit intellectual powers of understanding). Notice how, in this respect, you can never get to the general from the particular (and notice Hume's unidentified shift from "conceive" to "perceive"):

"Let man try to conceive a triangle in general, which is neither Isosceles nor Scalenum, nor has any particular length or proportion of sides; and he will soon perceive the absurdity of all the scholastic notions with regard to abstraction and general ideas."

On this mistaken philosophical path, Adler puts it succinctly:
"If all we have are sense-perceptions and images derived from sense, then we can never be aware of anything but a particular triangle."
and ...
An objective method of concept formation employs our ability to grasp concretes as things which are reducible to a common unit. We can do this WITHOUT antecedent concepts (words). Here is a catchy illustration of the beginning of the process:

When first defining "foot-long hotdogs," one method would be to quickly make an intuitive leap and argue that it means "panting poodles!" I believe that this is the process you are attacking when you attack Aristotle's methods as something requiring intuition - lacking objectivity in the assignment of "essences."

An objective method, however, would proceed differently. Let's take the first term first "foot-long." In regard to length, we know what a "foot" is, because we've seen one (it is an immediately perceptible unit; we can apply it without any appeal to other words). We can directly relate concretes to this unit to determine OBJECTIVELY whether a given concrete is to be excluded from the definition (by failing to correspond to the unit "foot").

Daniel, do you see where this is going (we will end with objectively formed definitions that are BOTH successfully differentiated AND refer to the facts of reality? Do you see how "every definition" DOES NOT require "an additional term?" Do you see how "changing the aim of this method from 'essences' to 'concepts', as Rand does," DOES "change the problem?"
and ...
" ... but this example has nothing to do with identity. The bent-stick illusion is a predicate statement, so A=A has nothing to tell us about it."

Brendan, it does have to do with identity. Saying " ... A=A has nothing to tell us about it." is inconsequential here - as I stated above: "A is A" is not meant to provide new knowledge (you're merely paraphrasing me while missing the point). For your quote to have relevance to my argument, wording must be changed to reflect emphasis on understanding, not on knowledge.

You say that the illusion is a predicate statement. Well then, let's pick our predicates and check for "A is A"s instrumentality in promoting a better understanding of reality:

One possible predicate to choose would be: "is bent" (the stick "is bent" when it is under water)

Another possible predicate to choose would be: "appears bent" (the stick "appears bent" when it is under water)

How do we choose between these? When faced with this choice, does "A is A" now have import (as an intellectual "guardrail" leading us to the truth of the matter)?

"A is A" allows us to effectively choose between rival predicates so that we can have informative (true) propositions at our disposal to dramatically aid in our understanding of the world and inform our decision-making while living on earth. It's just something that only has value when applied as a veridical constraint on the myriad of propositions a human mind is exposed to in the world. This is what I meant above when I said that a mind is (counter-intuitively) "empowered" by the constraints of reason and reality.

and ...
Bayesian: How in the heck can you be so certain of this - and especially without more empirical knowledge?

Aristotelian: Mechanistic understanding.

Bayesian: Sounds like a cool trick, I'll have to look into it - when I get time away from my liklihood ratios, that is.

Aristotelian: It's no "trick" - it's the proper use of your mind - you are a conceptual being.

Bayesian: Are you starting-in with that metaphysical stuff again?

Aristotelian: Yes ... I guess I can't help but to base my reasoning solidly in the actuality of reality.

Bayesian: Oh dear, where does all this mumbo-jumbo end?

Aristotelian: Actually, I can tell you that, too. You see, if you just work to understand these axioms here ...
 and ...
Excerpt from Adler's objective invalidation of Nominalism as a viable philosophical position
"If human beings enjoyed the power of conceptual, as opposed to perceptual thought, there would be no difficulty in explaining how words signify generalities or universals. They would derive their significance from concepts that give us our understanding of classes or kinds.

But regarding human beings as deprived of conceptual thought poses a problem for Berkeley and Hume. They are compelled to say that when we use words that appear to have general significance, we are applying them to a number of perceived individuals indifferently: that is, without any difference in the meaning of the word thus applied. This amounts to saying that there is a certain sameness in the individual things that the speaker or writer recognizes.

Are they not contradicting themselves when they offer this explanation of the meaning of general terms or common nouns? If human beings do not have conceptual thought, how can they recognize the sameness that permits the nominalists to say that the same word can be applied indifferently in a number of individuals?

Are they not contradicting themselves? Should not nominalism -- the assertion that names have general significance even though human beings can have no understanding of kinds or classes -- be rejected?"

source for excerpt:
http://www.thegreatideas.org/apd-nomi.html
and ...
Stanford: "Aquinas' distinction between essence and existence was not long unchallenged even among the Scholastics, being rejected early by Scotus and much later by Suarez. Descartes and Leibniz also denied it, and Hume took the same view, though for reasons peculiar to his own impression-based epistemology. Thus, he argued that ‘the idea of existence must either be derived from a distinct impression, conjoined with every perception or object of our thought, or must be the very same with the idea of the perception or object’. (Treatise of Human Nature, Bk.I, Part II, sect. vi) There being nothing to indicate the presence of any impression at all that is ‘conjoined with every perception or object of our thought’, he concludes that there is no distinct impression from which the idea of existence is derived. Rather, it is ‘the very same with the idea of what we conceive to be existent’. Any one dissenting from this, suggests Hume, has the task of indicating just what is the distinct idea from which the idea of existence derives."

Ed: First of all, and as I said above, Aquinas' distinction (which could have been prevented if he had listened to Abelard, by the way) is invalid - it stems from reading Aristotle's "O" the wrong way (so the rest is all "water under the bridge"). But to say something positively negative about Hume (so that critics have something to "chew on"), I'll continue. Hume's "impression-based epistemology" and consequent nominalism allowed him to make the error of cleaving the tie from his "impressions" to his "relations of ideas." In short, things did not have any intentional existence for him, "man" was a being without the distinctive powers of the intellect, and objectivity and (along with it) communication with others, was thereby made impossible (for him; and it must have been awful lonely for the poor soul - being the only one that knows what you are talking about!).
and ...
Stanford: "Hume's contention that the idea of existence ‘makes no addition’ to the idea of any object was to be reaffirmed in Kant"

Ed: And Kant's claim that there would be 2 kinds of philosophy - that which came before him, and that which would come later - was unfortunately prophetic (enter Ontological Idealism). In the spirit of contempt for Kant so characteristic of objectivists, allow me to claim that this was a man whose very psychological continuity was not real (noumenal) to him. In other words, his internal impressions of things were not "really" his internal impressions of things, but merely impressions of his impressions.
Ed


Post 199

Wednesday, May 25, 2005 - 8:39pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Brendan,

How would you establish the principle of mechanistic understanding? You can’t re-use the cookie cutter argument as I’ve outlined it, because that argument appeals to the principle without establishing it. So how would you arrive at the principle of mechanistic understanding without begging the question?

The cookie cutter argument (as you've outlined it) is insufficient. My cookie cutter argument, as intended, works with all tools. I picked a tool (cookie cutter) because tools are that of which we  NECESSARILY have mechanistic understanding. Think about the phenomenon of tool-making. How does it proceed, Brendan, other than directly THROUGH a mechanistic understanding? We DESIGN the mechanics to work, in general, in reality. Tools are special phenomena which can be--and often are--completely understood.

Ed


Post to this threadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Page 7Page 8Page 9Forward one pageLast Page


User ID Password or create a free account.