| | I quoted Cal, "(BTW Bill, an imaginary number is not a number that multiplied by itself equals minus one, for example 3i is an imaginary number, but multiplying it by itself results in -9)." And replied, "I never said it was. Go back and read the post from which you got that statement, and you'll see that I was quoting Prof. C. It was he who made that statement, not I."
He replied: You wrote, "The first sentence should read: 'An imaginary number is supposed to be that number which when multiplied by itself is equal to minus ONE.' This was probably clear from the context, but I just wanted to make it explicit so there's no misunderstanding, as the previous post was too old to edit." No, you didn't make that statement (and I never said you did), but you took the trouble to make a correction in it - 'so there's no misunderstanding' - without telling us that you think that the new version is still incorrect." I was correcting the quotation -- the attribution -- not the accuracy of the Professor's statement itself, since I misstated what Prof. C had said. You're right, I wasn't aware that he had misstated the theory. And I do appreciate your pointing it out. I'm not a mathematician, and didn't give the accuracy of his statement a second thought, since it didn't bear on the main point of the dialogue. I was concerned only with making sure that I had quoted him accurately. Sorry if I sounded defensive, but I didn't appreciate the suggestion that I agreed with the professor's erroneous definition, since I hadn't even considered the accuracy its content.
I wrote, "First, you assume that her use of 'arbitrary theory' applies to mathematical theories that have no practical application, when in fact that is not her position at all. Then you turn around and deny that mathematical theories with no practical application are arbitrary, while continuing to accuse her of holding that they are, when it was you who attributed that position to her in the first place. I don't know if there's a term for this kind of fallacy, but if there isn't, there should be."
You replied, Really? Conveniently you omit the relevant statement by Rand, so I'll repeat it here:
If you tell me that the concept, let's say, of an imaginary number doesn't do anything in reality, but somebody builds a theory on it, then I would say it is an invalid concept. [emphasis added] Cal, I think that by "reality" in this context, she is referring to the fact that a process of abstract measurement can have a potential application in the real world, even if it doesn't presently have one. I think the context bears this out, if you go back and reread the entire dialogue. (See below) This after Prof. C had said:
It turns out that it has a great usefulness as a device mathematically for solving problems of a real kind--for instance, problems involving electrical circuits.[emphasis added]
So there's no misunderstanding about what is meant by "reality" in this dialogue: it is the physical world. And it's obvious that Rand thinks a mathematical concept is invalid if it can't be applied to solve problems in the physical world. If I understood you correctly, you'll agree that this is a ridiculous notion. But the fact remains that it is exactly what Rand said here, no matter how you try to rewrite history by telling us that Rand didn't mean it. Nobody's trying to rewrite history here. Let's recap the dialogue: Prof. C: It turns out that it has a great usefulness as a device mathematically for solving problems of a real kind--for instance, problems involving electrical circuits. But I personally do not see the validity of this concept. There is nothing in reality to which it corresponds. Nothing is measured except by real numbers.
AR: But here there is a certain contradiction in your theoretical presentation. If you say that these imaginary numbers do serve a certain function in measurement, then--
Prof C: Excuse me, not in measurements of anything, but in computation--in solving an equation.
AR: The main question is: do they really serve that purpose?
Prof. C: In practice, yes.
AR: If they serve that purpose, then they have a valid meaning--only then they are not concepts of entities, they are concepts of method. If they have a use which you can apply to actual reality, but they do not correspond to any actual numbers, it is clearly a concept pertaining to method. It is an epistemological device to establish certain relationships. But then it has validity. All concepts of this kind are concepts of method and have to be clearly differentiated as such. Let's stop here and consider what has just been said. Observe that Prof C says, "...not in measurements of anything, but in computation--in solving an equation." To which Rand replies, "The main question is: do they really serve that purpose?" Prof. C answers, "In practice, yes. To which Rand replies, "If they serve that purpose, then they have a valid meaning... Whenever in doubt, incidentally, about the standing of any concept, you can do what I have done in this discussion right now. I asked you, "What, in reality, does that concept refer to?" If you tell me that the concept, let's say, of an imaginary number doesn't do anything in reality, but somebody builds a theory on it, then I would say it is an invalid concept. But if you tell me, yes, this particular concept, although it doesn't correspond to anything real, does achieve certain ends in computations, then clearly you can classify it: it is a concept of method, and it acquires meaning only in the context of a certain process of computation. I believe that by "do anything in reality," Rand would include the potential practical application of a process of computation. Remember, this is an extemporaneous dialogue, so we have to cut her a little slack here. When Prof. C says, "Not in measurements of anything, but in computation," Rand is clearly in agreement, which suggests that she doesn't regard the actual measurement of existents to be a necessary condition for the validity of the concept. She considers abstract computation to be sufficient. She clearly recognizes that mathematics is a science of method, which may not have an immediate practical application, but could have in the future.
I asked Cal, "'[W]hat, in your view, does a number like 5 refer to? As I've indicated, it cannot refer only to itself, so what does it refer to? Doesn't it have to refer to five somethings--to five existents of some kind? The referent of 5 is not 5; it is | | | | |." He replied, You still don't get it: in mathematical number theory numbers do not "refer to somethings", they are an abstract construction that may have once originated from the kindergarten arithmetic you mention, but no they longer depend on such primitive notions for their definition (and sentiments have nothing to do with it)." The point is that they must refer to some quantitative unit, but may refer to any, which is what makes them abstract rather than concrete. The concept 5 refers to what is common to any group of 5 units. The concept is unintelligible without this reference. You can't make sense out of it unless you understand it in terms of a certain number of discrete units. They can be any kind of units, but they must be some kind. The five vertical lines are stand-ins for any five units, whether they be apples, oranges, cats, dogs, whatever. If you don't agree with this, then please tell me what 5 refers to, and what you understand it to mean.
- Bill
|
|