| | Hi David,
What browser are you using? If you're using Safari or Firefox, you're limited to the gimpy textbox and won't be able to gray out your quotations without using html codes. If you have a PC instead of a Mac and are using Explorer, you should see the formatting that enables you to highlight your quotes.
You wrote, I think highly of H.W. B. Joseph, who was one of the greatest of all philosophical critics, but here he wrongly assumes that an object's nature allows it to act in only one way. Why assume this? If, as you recognize in what you say about my criticism of Peikoff, it makes sense to say that a human being need not always choose the same way in the same conditions, why must non-human entities always operate in the same way? Well, everything "must" act according to its nature, so in that sense it must always act "the same" way. An orange tree cannot bear lemons; a dog cannot give birth to a cat, and inanimate matter is not goal-directed, as living organisms are. Unlike human beings, it is not in the nature of non-volitional entities to choose between alternative courses of action. So, we have no reason to believe that a meteor falls from the sky or that the earth revolves around the sun because it chooses to, although we do have reason to believe that human beings behave the way they do because they choose to.
I wrote, "Yes they did [have to exist], in the sense that no alternative to them was possible. To say it’s possible for them not to have existed doesn’t make any sense. How could they not have existed? They were not created in the first place. They’re existentially primary." You are just restating the Objectivist view that the entities that exist have to exist, not offering an argument. What is supposed to be the contradiction in thinking that other entities than the ones that in fact exist could have existed? If someone says that a round square could exist, we can readily grasp why what he says is contradictory. But to say that the entities that actually exist might not have existed is contradictory only if the entities that now exist could not have failed to exist. But that thesis is just what I am questioning. To appeal to it in order to refute me blatantly begs the question. All right. Then please tell me how the fundamental constituents of the universe (which were not created and were here from the beginning, as it were) could have failed to exist. They were not created, so there is no creator that could have chosen otherwise -- that could have created something different instead. So, how could these primary existents have failed to exist? The possibility of an alternative -- i.e., of non-existence -- simply doesn't apply to them. There have been people who have claimed that God can violate the laws of logic---I think that Descartes held this. But it has certainly not been the dominant opinion among the Scholastics, or among Jews and Christians generally. Peikoff's short proof of atheism isn't worth much if it addresses a concept of God different from that held by orthodox believers. Well, if theists don't believe that God can violate the laws of logic, then on what grounds do they believe that God can perform miracles? A miracle is a violation of the law of identity. A thing cannot act in contradiction to its nature. No matter how powerful God is, he cannot perform miracles, he cannot cause existents to act in contradiction to their natures; he is limited by natural law. If your reply is, but God can change their natures, how? Even he has to work within the limits of what exists, and what exists has identity at the most fundamental level. Quoting Bacon, "Nature to be commanded must be obeyed."
I wrote, "approval and disapproval imply the possibility of choice." On the Objectivist view, a value is something that one acts to gain or keep. If approval and disapproval are tied to this notion of value, then one can't approve or disapprove of what can't be altered. Approval and disapproval are tied to moral value -- to that which one ought to value. A robber values -- acts to gain and keep -- other people's money, but that doesn't mean that he ought to value it -- that he ought to gain and keep it. We can still disapprove of the robber's values and his actions. But why should one think that approval and disapproval are limited to what we can value, in terms of the Objectivist concept of value? It's not limited to the Objectivist concept of value; it's limited to the concept of choice -- of what can be altered or changed. You have a surpassing knowledge of Objectivist philosophy, based on what is obviously a great many years of careful study and thought; but I must say that you seem to find it difficult to think outside the Objectivist framework. Your response to an objection is often to repeat the thesis that is being challenged. Thanks for the compliment . . . I think. :-/
I wrote, "Peikoff would say that you can’t have knowledge of reality ahead of any contact with it." In other words, there aren't innate ideas because there aren't innate ideas. Again, you respond to a question on why an Objectivist view is true by reiterating the Objectivist view. I wasn't just reiterating the Objectivist view. I was giving a reason for it. You didn't ask me to justify specifically that reason. Isn't an idea a generalization from experience? How could you be born with already formed concepts or ideas?
I wrote, "Not the concept; he doesn’t need the concept to perform this process. He can observe the similarities of the three objects against a background of difference, which is how one forms concepts in the first place. . . . It does not presuppose concepts. You need more familiarity with Objectivist epistemology to understand the theory. I have no doubt that my knowledge of Objectivist epistemology is deficient, but I'm not here making the mistake of thinking that Objectivists think that observing similarities requires concepts. Rather, I'm denying, or at least questioning, that one could observe similarities in the absence of concepts. This is a very common criticism of abstractionist theories of concept formation, raised by Jerry Fodor and Peter Geach, among others. So you're saying that, in the absence of concepts, one cannot see that A is more like B than either is to C? -- that you cannot perceive similarities and differences -- that it's conceptual rather than perceptual? I don't think so. Animals can perceive similarities and difference, but they cannot abstract from their perception of them. They can perceive and recognize the differences between (say) dogs and cats, but they cannot arrive at the abstraction 'dog' or 'cat'. Yes, you are certainly right that "red" does not mean "growing on a tree". But then you can't say, as Peikoff does, that "[A] concept designates existents, including all their characteristics, whether definitional or not." "Red" designates all red objects. Some of these red objects have the property of growing on trees, i.e.,this is one of the characteristics of these red objects. But then by Peikoff's statement, these characteristics become part of the designation of "red". One can then ask, what does "growing on a tree" designate? One must fill in the designations of "growing" and "tree." The process that Peikoff describes is recursive. It is in this way that you will soon get that most concepts refer to most things that exist. I think I see the problem. The term "existent" in Peikoff's statement does not simply mean entity. An existent, according to Rand, is anything that exists, be it a thing, an attribute or an action. So, the concept "red" designates an existent, because it designates an attribute of an entity. So when Peikoff says that a concept designates existents, including all their characteristics, whether definitional or not, he is referring, in the case of an attribute, to all of the characteristics of the attribute of the entity, not to all the characteristics of the entity of which it is an attribute. So, in the case of an apple, the concept "red" designates all of the characteristics of the color of the apple, including its hue, shade, brightness, area, etc., not all of the characteristics of the apple itself.
I wrote, "Well, they’re integrations of perceptual knowledge, but that doesn’t mean that they can’t be extended to cover future instances of the concepts they’ve integrated." Here I suggest that you are guilty of the fallacy of the stolen concept, in that what you say is perfectly true of our ordinary language concept of "concept", but you carry this over without justification to the Objectivist theory of concepts. In the ordinary language concept of "concept", a concept has a definition that give a sense, not a reference. Here, anything that meets the terms of the definition falls under the concept. But on the Objectivist view, as Peikoff states it, a concept is an abstraction, derived by "measurement omission" from concretes, and it designates the concretes from which it has been abstracted. A new concrete would then demand a new concept, because by hypothesis the new concrete is not part of the designation of the original concept. It designates the concretes from which it has been abstracted, yes, and all relevantly similar concretes as well. Why do you assume that just because it has been abstracted from a certain number of objects that it must refer only to those objects and not to any others that are relevantly similar? Once you've formed the concept from observation, you can recognize that any new concretes that fall within that range can be classified under the concept. You don't need to form a new concept, and it would obviously be inappropriate to do so.
I wrote, "He’s not saying that one must choose to be alive in order to choose; he’s saying that unless one’s existence depends on certain actions, one cannot value. . . . It may help to realize that the essential point of the robot example is that values depend on having something to gain or lose by your actions. True, if heaven and hell existed, they would be enough to justify the existence of values to an immortal being. However, because they don’t exist and are mere religious fantasies, the reality is that values depend on the existence of life and on the happiness or suffering that results from actions that are beneficial or harmful to it." But the point here isn't whether heaven and hell exist: it's rather that if you agree with the conclusion of my thought experiment, then it's wrong that the concept of value conceptually depends on the possibility that one can choose between life and death. It doesn't depend on the possibility that one It doesn't, for these immortal beings; and if you accept what I say, then you have rejected the conclusion that Rand and Peikoff draw from the immortal robot story. If you now say,"But it does depend on this choice for beings like us", I would respond, why? Why does what matters to us rest on the possibility that we can cease to exist? Again, the point of the analogy is to show that value presupposes that one has something to gain or lose by one's actions. Then you have to recognize that gaining or losing something is possible only to a living organism. There is no heaven or hell. There is no spiritual immortality. In doing philosophy, you have to respect the facts of reality. You cannot continue to deal in fantasies and use these as a basis for drawing conclusions about life and values. This is probably one of the biggest mistakes contemporary philosopher's make. Their orientation is not reality centered. Intellectually, they don't live in the real world, but in an academic ivory tower.
I wrote, "Values are connected to life-promoting action. That which is life promoting tends to give rise to pleasure or happiness, and that which is harmful tends to result in pain or suffering. The existence of value is strictly a function of biology -- of the organism's goal of self-preservation." This strikes me as true of many values, but I don't see why having a tendency to promote life is a necessary condition for pleasure. Why can't some pleasurable activities be neutral in their effect on life? Eating ice cream in moderation can be very pleasurable; but although, I don't think it is harmful, it is hardly life enhancing. Well, it is in the sense that one's desire for it is based on one's need for calories, which are themselves required for survival. Thanks once more for your comments: I really appreciate them. If I may say so, I'm also grateful for your calm and matter-of-fact tone in responding to my very negative comments on Peikoff's book. My review gives in part a misleading impression, in that someone reading it alone would be likely to think that my attitude toward Objectivism is much more negative than it in fact is. Whether rightly or wrongly, I formed a very unfavorable impression of Peikoff, and my animus in the review is directed toward him rather than Objectivism as such. I have reviewed other Objectivist philosophers and Objectivist sympathizers much more positively. Understood. One question in conclusion. You said in your original post that my philosophy was "rationalistic". Other Objectivists have also said this about me, but I don't have a good grasp of what is meant by this. I'd be grateful if you would say something more about this. Sure. For Objectivists, a rationalist is someone who "obtains his knowledge of the world by deducing it exclusively from concepts, which come from inside his head and are not derived form the perception of physical facts . . ." (Rand, For the New Intellectual 31.) I think you reflect that orientation when you question that concepts are gained through experience, and when you consider religious fantasies an important consideration in determining the nature and source of value. Deduction and thought experiments are fine as far as they go, but they cannot serve as the ultimate source of knowledge. Induction -- observation of the real world -- must be our epistemological foundation.
(Edited by William Dwyer on 5/18, 5:37pm)
|
|